Mostrar el registro sencillo del ítem

dc.contributor.advisorEspejo Serna,Juan Camilo
dc.contributor.authorGómez Sánchez, Tatiana
dc.date.accessioned2019-09-24T19:48:34Z
dc.date.available2019-09-24T19:48:34Z
dc.date.issued2019-08-05
dc.identifier.urihttp://hdl.handle.net/10818/37410
dc.description109 páginases_CO
dc.description.abstractEl estudio filosófico permite adentrarse en una gran variedad de temas y objetos, de los cuales formula distintas preguntas y problemas; cuestiones en las que se adentra buscando encontrar un poco de luz. Esta versatilidad que tiene la filosofía para adoptar una cuestión como suya es una cualidad que, con respeto y cuidado, pretendo tomar como punto de partida de este estudio. En este caso, el tema u objeto a tratar será tomado de una disciplina en particular: la música. Es, entonces, el estudio filosófico de la música la primera respuesta a la pregunta qué estamos haciendo en este trabajo. La filosofía de la música estudia las cuestiones fundamentales acerca de la naturaleza y valor de la música, así como también de nuestra experiencia con ella (Kania 2017). Estas cuestiones pueden referirse al lenguaje, al significado y expresividad de la música, preguntándose, por ejemplo, qué expresa una obra musical, si tiene o no un significado, y, de ser así, si tiene o determina algún tipo de valor.es_CO
dc.language.isospaes_CO
dc.publisherUniversidad de La Sabanaes_CO
dc.rightsAttribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International*
dc.rights.urihttp://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/*
dc.sourceUniversidad de La Sabana
dc.sourceIntellectum Repositorio Universidad de La Sabana
dc.sourceUniversidad de La Sabana
dc.sourceIntellectum Repositorio Universidad de La Sabana
dc.subjectFilosofíaes_CO
dc.subjectMúsicaes_CO
dc.subjectComunicaciónes_CO
dc.titleLa improvisación musical y la teoría tipo/instancia de las obras musicaleses_CO
dc.typebachelorThesises_CO
dc.publisher.programFilosofía
dc.publisher.departmentFacultad de Filosofía y Ciencias Humanas
dc.identifier.local273928
dc.identifier.localTE10308
dc.rights.accessRightsopenAccess
dc.creator.degreeFilósofo
dcterms.referencesAlperson, P. (1984). On musical improvisation. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 43(1), 17-29.eng
dcterms.referencesAlperson, P. (2010). A topography of improvisation. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 68(3), 273-280eng
dcterms.referencesApel, W. (1969). Harvard Dictionary of Music. 2d. Cambridge, Mass: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.eng
dcterms.referencesArmstrong, D. M. (1989). Universals: An Opinionated Introduction. Boulder: Westview Press.eng
dcterms.referencesBailey, D. (1993). Improvisation: Its Nature and Practice in Music. United States of America: Da Capo Press.eng
dcterms.referencesBalaguer, M. (2016). Platonism in Metaphysics. Edward N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Recuperado de: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2016/entries/platonism/eng
dcterms.referencesBerendt, J. (1994). El Jazz: De Nueva Orleans al Jazz Rock. Santafé de Bogotá: Fondo de Cultura Económico.spa
dcterms.referencesBerliner, P. (1994). Thinking in Jazz: The Infinite Art of Improvisation. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.eng
dcterms.referencesBertinetto, A. (2012). Paganini Does Not Repeat. Musical Improvisation and the Type/Token Ontology. Teorema, 31(3), 105-126.eng
dcterms.referencesBrown, L. (1996). Musical Works, Improvisation, and the Principle of Continuity. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 54(4), 353-369.eng
dcterms.referencesBrown, L. (2000). Feeling my way: Jazz Improvisation and Its Vicissitudes–A Plea for Imperfection. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 68(3), 273-280.eng
dcterms.referencesCaplan, B. & Matheson, C. (2006). Defending Musical Perdurantism. British Journal of Aesthetics, 46(1), 59-69.eng
dcterms.referencesDavies, S. (2001). Musical Works and Performances: A Philosophical Exploration, Oxford: Oxford University Press.eng
dcterms.referencesDodd, J. (2007). Works of Music: An Essay in Ontology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.eng
dcterms.referencesDodd, J. (2008). Musical Works: Ontology and Meta-Ontology. Philosophy Compass, 3(6), 1113-1134.eng
dcterms.referencesDyck, J. (2014). Perfect Compliance in Musical History and Musical Ontology. The British Journal of Aesthetics, 54(1), 31-47.eng
dcterms.referencesGoodman, N. (1968). Languages of Art: An Approach to a Theory of Symbols. United States of America: The Bobbs-Merrill Company Inc.eng
dcterms.referencesHowell, R. (2002). Types, Indicated and Initiated. British Journal of Aesthetics, 42(2), 105-127.eng
dcterms.referencesJeppesen, K. (1939). Counterpoint. The Polyphonic Vocal Style of the Sixteenth Century. New York: Dover Publications.eng
dcterms.referencesKamien, R. (1976). Music: An appreciation. New York: McGraw-Hill.eng
dcterms.referencesKania, A. (2008). The Methodology of Musical Ontology: Descriptivism and Its Implications. British Jounal of Aesthetics, 48(10), 426-444.eng
dcterms.referencesKania, A. (2011). All Play and No Work: An Ontology of Jazz. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 69(4), 391-403.eng
dcterms.referencesKania, A. (2017). The Philosophy of Music. Edward N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Recuperado de: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/music/eng
dcterms.referencesKaplan, D. (1990). Words. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 64(1), 93-119.eng
dcterms.referencesKerman, J., Tomlinson, G., & Kerman, V. (2012). Listen. Boston: Bedford/St. Martin's.eng
dcterms.referencesKernfeld, B. (1988). Harmony. In The New Grove Dictionary of Jazz. (Vol 2). London: Macmillan.eng
dcterms.referencesKivy, P. (1980). The Corded Shell: Reflections on Musical Expression. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.eng
dcterms.referencesKivy, P. (1983a). Platonism in Music: A Kind of Defense. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 19(1), 109-129.eng
dcterms.referencesKivy, P. (1983b). Platonism in Music: Another Kind of Defense. American Philosophical Quarterly, 24(3), 245-252.eng
dcterms.referencesKivy, P. (1984). The Corded Shell: Reflections on Musical Expression. Philosophy and Rhetoric, 17(1), 47-55.eng
dcterms.referencesKivy, P. (1989). Sound Sentiment: An Essay on the Musical Emotions, including the complete text of “The Corded Shell”. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.eng
dcterms.referencesKivy, P. (1993). The Fine Art of Repetition: Essays in the Philosophy of Music. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.eng
dcterms.referencesLevinson, J. (1978). Properties and Related Entities. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 39(1), 1-22.eng
dcterms.referencesLevinson, J. (1980). What a Musical Work Is. Journal of Philosophy, 77(1), 5-28.eng
dcterms.referencesLevinson, J. (1992). Review of D. M. Armstrong’s Universals: An Opinionated Introduction. The Philosophical Review, 101(3), 654-660.eng
dcterms.referencesPredelli, S. (1995). Against Musical Platonism. British Journal of Aesthetics, 35(4), 338-350.eng
dcterms.referencesPredelli, S. (1999a). Goodman and the Score. British Journal of Aesthetics, 39(2), 138-147.eng
dcterms.referencesPredelli, S. (1999b). Goodman and the Wrong Note Paradox. British Journal of Aesthetics, 39(4), 364-375.eng
dcterms.referencesPredelli, S. (2001). Musical Ontology and the Argument from Creation. British Journal of Aesthetics, 41(3), 279-292.eng
dcterms.referencesLoux, M. (2006). Metaphysics: A Contemporary Introduction. New York: Routledge.eng
dcterms.referencesMoelants, D. (Ed.). (2014). Improvising Early Music: The History of Musical Improvisation from the Late Middle Ages to the Early Baroque. Leuven, Belgium: Leuven University Press.eng
dcterms.referencesNirala, S. (2015). Cadenza. In The Editors of Encyclopaedia Britannica (Ed.), Encyclopaedia Britannica. Recuperado de: https://www.britannica.com/art/cadenzaeng
dcterms.referencesNorden, H. (1969). Fundamental Counterpoint. Boston: Crescendo Publishing Company.eng
dcterms.referencesRandel, D. M. (1986). The New Harvard Dictionary of Music. Cambridge: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.eng
dcterms.referencesSadie, S., & Tyrrell, J. (2001). Improvisation. In The New Grove Dictionary of Music and Musicians. (Vol 12, pp. 94-133). London: Macmillan.eng
dcterms.referencesSampaolo, M. (2014). Variation. In The Editors of Encyclopaedia Britannica (Ed.), Encyclopaedia Britannica. Recuperado de: https://www.britannica.com/art/musical variationeng
dcterms.referencesStecker, R. (2003). Interpretation and Construction: Art, Speech, and the Law. Malden, MA: Blackwell.eng
dcterms.referencesRohrbaugh, G. (2003). Artworks as Historical Individuals. European Journal of Philosophy, 11(2), 177-205.eng
dcterms.referencesRumfitt, I. (1993). Content and Context: The Paratactic Theory Revisited and Revised. Mind, 102(407), 429-454.eng
dcterms.referencesThomasson, A. (2006). Debates about the Ontology of Art: What are We Doing Here? Philosophy Compass, 1(3), 245-255.eng
dcterms.referencesWetzel, L (2018). Types and Tokens. Edward N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Recuperado de https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/types-tokens/eng
dcterms.referencesWollheim, R. (1968). Art and its Objects. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.eng
dcterms.referencesWolterstorff, N. (1980). Works and Worlds of Art. Oxford: Clarendon Press.eng
dcterms.referencesYoung, J. & Matheson, C. (2000). The Metaphysics of Jazz. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 58(2), 125-134.eng
dcterms.referencesZemach, E. (1970). Four Ontologies. Journal of Philosophy, 67(8), 231-247.eng


Ficheros en el ítem

Thumbnail

Este ítem aparece en la(s) siguiente(s) colección(ones)

Mostrar el registro sencillo del ítem

Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 InternationalExcepto si se señala otra cosa, la licencia del ítem se describe como Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International